History, Big History, & Metahistory
DOI: 10.37911/9781947864023.06
6. The Star Gazer & the Flesh Eater: Elements of a Theory of Metahistory
Author: David C. Krakauer, Santa Fe Institute
Excerpt
Historical Modes: Particular Events and General Trends
When considering these two quotes from Newton’s early and late scholarship [23, 24], we can discern a significant shift of interest and of approach or method. In the Principia, Newton sought to reconcile the regular motion through space and time of all massive bodies, regardless of size, position or composition. The tone is one of parsimonious reasoning coupled to a mild contempt for storytelling or “hypotheses.” In the Chronology, Newton provides a list of names and places which he sought to tether to an objective astronomical calendar. There is no effort to discern regulatory, only a temporal sequence. These two perspectives can be seen to constitute two poles of historical inquiry, one mechanistic and regular, and the other, incidental and particular. This tension lies at the core of most, if not all, historical inquiries. In this chapter I shall outline a few of the implications of these polarizing tendencies of history through the lens of evolutionary biology and complexity science, and search for a means of overcoming them through an appropriate transdisciplinary language. The example of Newton serves to establish that these two approaches to dynamics can reside within the same research mind and program, and secondarily, serves to preemptively refute a few of the more tendentious dichotomies that arise in discussions between the “star-gazing” scientist and “flesh-eating” humanist.
I take the position that historical explanation (as opposed to historical recreation or reconstruction in the form of systematic description and other forms of historical scene-setting and portraiture) seeks to account for some pattern of behavior in what we might call the arbitrary present. The arbitrary present (AP), in contrast to the chronological present (CP)—the temporal now. The arbitrary present is any date over the course of history for which we seek an explanation in terms of a series of antecedent events. The AP could just as well be 1492, 1687, 1914, or 2050. This idea was articulated, somewhat furtively, by Braudel when he suggested that “is it not the secret aim and underlying motive of history to seek to explain the present?” [2]. Perhaps this is the primary aim of history, and that reconstruction of the past is a step towards this goal, and not the natural terminus of historical inquiry. I will have much to say about “events” in the course of this argument. The claim is that when historians move towards the analysis of well-curated, quantitative data sets in the near future, this concept will again become central, as it will be necessary to organize observations in a time series, and events will represent preferred and principled levels of granularity for these observations.
Newton’s work reveals at least two tendencies, or modes of historical explanation (these are in contrast to non-historical means of accounting for the AP which I shall discuss shortly). One historical mode is to enumerate, in as much detail as there are facts available, the causal sequence of events culminating in the desired variables describing the AP. Hence if we are interested in the colonial history of Mexico, to take one classic example [25]:
While at Cempoalla Cortes received a message from Escalante, his commander at Villa Rica, informing him there were four strange ships hovering off the coast, and that they took no notice of his repeated signals. This intelligence greatly alarmed the general, who feared they might be a squadron sent by the governor of Cuba to interfere with his movements. In much haste, he set out at the head of a few horsemen, and, ordering a party of light infantry to follow, posted back to Villa Rica. The rest of the army he left in charge of Alvarado and of Gonzalo de Sandoval, a young officer, who had begun to give evidence of the uncommon qualities which have secured him so distinguished a rank among the conquerors of Mexico.
—William H. Prescott,
History of the Conquest of Mexico
References
[1] Bennett, C.H. “How to Define Complexity in Physics, and Why.” In Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information, Edited by W. H. Zurek, 137-148. Redwood City, CA: Addison Wesley, 1990.
[2] Braudel, Fernand. A History of Civilizations. New York, NY: Penguin Group, 1995.
[3] Herodotus. The Histories. Translated by: Donald Lateiner and G C Macaulay. New York: Barnes & Noble Inc., 2004.
[4] Crow, John A. The Epic of Latin America, Fourth Edition. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1992.
[5] Dawkins, R. The Selfish Gene. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1989.
[6] de Visser, J.A.G.M., J. Hermisson, G.P. Wagner, L. Ancel Meyers, H. Bagheri-Chaichian, J.L. Blanchard, L. Chao, J.M. Cheverud, S.F. Elena, W. Fontana, G. Gibson, T.F. Hansen, D. Krakauer, R.C. Lewontin, C. Ofria, S.H. Rice, G. von Dassow, A. Wagner, and M.C. Whitlock. “Evolution and Detection of Genetic Robustness.” Evolution 57 (2003): 1959-1972.
[7] Diamond, Jared. Guns, Germs, and Steel, First Edition. New York: W. W. Norton, 1997.
[8] Doyle, Sir Arthur Conan. A Study in Scarlet. United Kingdom: Ward Lock & Co., 1887.
[9] Ferguson, Kitty. Tycho and Kepler: The Unlikely Partnership that Forever Changed our Understanding of the Heavens. New York, NY: Walker & Company, 2004.
[10] Fischer, David Hackett. Historians’ Fallacies; Toward a Logic of Historical Thought. New York: HarperCollins, 1970.
[11] Frank, S.A., and M. Slatkin. “Fisher’s Fundamental Theorem of Natural Selection.” Trends in Ecology & Evolution 7 (1992): 92-95.
[12] Fudenberg, Drew, and Jean Tirole. Game Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991.
[13] Gell-Mann, M., and S. Lloyd. “Information Measures, Effective Complexity, and Total Information.” Complexity 2(1) (1998): 44-52.
[14] Gibbon, Edward. The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire. Boston, MA: Adamant Media Corp., 2000.
[15] Gould, Stephen Jay. The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. New York, NY: Harvard University Press, 2002.
[16] Keller, Laurent. Levels of Selection in Evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999.
[17] Kimura, Motoo. The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
[18] Kirkwood, Burton. The History of Mexico. New York: St. Martin’s Griffin, 2005.
[19] Krakauer, D. C. “Evolution, Complexity and Metahistoricism.” Nouvelles perspectives en sciences sociales 4 (2009): 53-67.
[20] Lewis, G. N., and M. Randall. Thermodynamics, Second Edition. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1961.
[21] Nagel, Ernest. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961.
[22] Namier, Lewis Bernstein. In the Margin of History. Manchester, NH: Ayer Publishing, 1967.
[23] Newton, Isaac. The Chronology of Ancient Kingdoms Amended (1728). Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing, 2010.
[24] Newton, Isaac. Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687). Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing, 2007.
[25] Prescott, William H. History of the Conquest of Mexico. The Modern Library. New York, NY: Random House, 1843, 2001 Edition.
[26] Smith, J., and E. Szathmáry. The Major Transitions in Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.
[27] Thomas, Hugh. The Spanish Civil War. New York, NY: Simon & Schuster, 1994.
[28] Vilar, Pierre. “The Age of Don Quixote.” New Left Review, I/68, 1971.