Turing’s Brainchild: Artificial Intelligence

Foundational Papers in Complexity Science pp. 293–333
DOI: 10.37911/9781947864528.11

Turing’s Brainchild: Artificial Intelligence

Author: Daniel Dennett, Tufts University; Santa Fe Institute; and New College of the Humanities, London

 

Excerpt

In 1950, the mathematician Alan Turing was one of a handful of people in the world who had any experience in computer programming, and he was already coming to terms with the enormous implications of the new digital world he had helped create. He quite appropriately published his reflections in Mind, the leading philosophy journal in the English-speaking world. It became an instant classic, inspiring thousands of discussions of what soon became known as the Turing Test, the “imitation game” that he proposed as a worthy replacement for the tiresome argument that was already well under way in 1949 about whether these new machines could think—the way we human beings can.

Can machines think? Turing declared that this question is “too meaningless to deserve discussion.” Instead of taking sides in debates about how to define these terms, he restricted his attention to a crisply definable task: winning the imitation game, in which a “discrete state machine” vies with a human being to see which can convince a human judge— through a telecommunicated conversation—of its humanity. This move is often seen as behavioristic—handsome is as handsome does—but it is better seen as just scientific: whatever thinking is, it should be something we can observe unmistakably if indirectly through its objective effects in the world. We may have our doubts about the suitability of Turing’s replacement, but at least we will know whether some entity passes the test—like the net on the basketball hoop, the test would serve an important epistemological purpose, turning delicate and unreliable judgments into indisputable results.

Bibliography

Block, N. 1978. “Troubles with Functionalism.” Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9:261–325.

https://hdl.handle.net/11299/185298.

. 1982. “Psychologism and Behaviorism.” Philosophical Review 90:5–43. https://doi.org/10.2307/

2184371.

Dennett, D. 1985. “Can Machines Think?” In How We Know, edited by M. Shafto, 121–145. San Francisco, CA: Harper and Row.

—. 1987. “Fast Thinking.” In The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

—. 2013. “The Chinese Room.” In Intuition Pumps and Other Tools for Thinking. New York, NY: Norton.

—. 2019. “What Can We Do?” In 25 Ways of Looking at AI, edited by J. Brockman, 41–53. New York, NY: Penguin.

Descartes, R. [1637]1960. Discourse on Method. Translated by L. Lafleur. New York, NY: Bobbs Merrill.

French, R. M. 1990. “Subcognition and the Limits of the Turing Test.” Mind 99:433–460. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCIX.393.53.

—. 2000. “The Chinese Room: Just Say ‘No!’” Proceedings of the 22nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, 657–662. https://escholarship.org/uc/item/9062452s.

Gallistel, C. R. (forthcoming). “The Neurological Bases for the Computational Theory of Mind.” In a festschrift for Jerry Fodor.

Goodhart, C. 1975. “Problems of Monetary Management: The UK Experience.” In Papers in Monetary Economics, vol. 1. Sydney, Australia: Reserve Bank of Australia.

Haugeland, J. 1985. Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

La Mettrie, J. O. de. 1747. L’Homme Machine.

Lucas, J. R. 1961. “Minds, Machines, and Gödel.” Philosophy 36:112–127. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819100057983.

Penrose, R. 1989. The Emperor’s New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

—. 1990. “The Non-Algorithmic Mind.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4): 692–705. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X0008105X.

Searle, J. 1980. “Minds, Brains, and Programs.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3:417–424. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00005756.

Smith, J. I., and Y. Y. Haddad. 1975. “Women in the Afterlife: The Islamic View as Seen from Qur’ān and Tradition.” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 43 (1): 39–50. https://doi.org/10.1093/jaarel/XLIII.1.39.

BACK TO Foundational Papers in Complexity Science